Conservatives who are lower in nonspecific
needs for closure
but have high needs for specific closure with regards to, for example, God and
government, may be relatively more open to change and uncertainty that is an
outcome of their decision to reject prevalent modernist norms and even to
militate against them. Jost et al (2003b), for example, have suggested that
progressive revolutionaries should be highly open to change and uncertainty,
reactionary revolutionaries moderately open, established socialist and
communist regimes also moderately open, and traditional hierarchical regimes
not at all open.
However, Jost et al. (2003b) ignore differences among the
progressive revolutionaries—some of whom may be seeking to instantiate values
based on a transcendental truth, others of whom may believe that they have an
empirically verifiable truth.
The Worldview Model suggests that progressive
revolutionaries should have different closure needs depending on their
traditionalist, modern, or post-modern orientations. Their level of
integrative complexity, responsiveness to salient beliefs and values, and
tolerance of change should vary with the specific and nonspecific closure needs
specific to their version of traditionalism, modernism, or postmodernism.
Self-identified liberals may also embrace beliefs that could
reflect postmodernist absolute uncertainty (Golec & Van Bergh, 2007), but
are instead firmly modernist. For example, these liberals could
embrace scientific inquiry and believe that it allows them to know absolute
truth. These same liberals, however, could claim to respect other
forms of knowledge. This could be because liberals in general tend to value
novel experience and are generally lower in closure needs (Jost et al.,
2003a). This could also be because the modernist perspective
encourages a sense of personal uncertainty and some modernists may generalize
from their lack of personal ability to achieve certainty in certain domains to
a belief that no living person can achieve certainty in those domains.
Alternate beliefs, to these modernists, can be accepted because everyone
operates under the same conditions of inescapable uncertainty.
Liberals with relatively more certainty about their own
ability to know may be both higher in need for closure and engage in more moral
exporting (proselytizing), although I know of no studies directly assessing
liberal this relationship. Peterson, Smith, Tannenbaum, and Shaw
(2009) demonstrated that the relationship between moral exporting behaviors and
conservative identification can be mediated by both the need for closure and moral
absolutism. Using a sample of undergraduates at the University of Utah and
administering a bipolar scale of liberal to conservative identification, as
well as new scales developed to measure moral absolutism and moral exporting,
the authors found that moral exporting was positively related to conservatism.
This relationship varied by religious affiliation, with both moral exporting
and moral absolutism being positive correlated with religious attendance.
Mormonism was more highly correlated with moral exporting than other religious
affiliations. While need for closure correlated positively with conservatism,
moral exporting, and moral absolutism, moral absolutism was a more proximate
mediator of the relationship between conservatism and moral exporting.
It is possible that liberals who are high in moral
absolutism (which modernist liberals should be when and if they believe in
their own ability to make rational moral judgments) and higher in need for
closure will engage in moral exporting. The Worldview Model would predict that
liberals who possess relatively fewer closure-avoidant beliefs should engage in
more moral exporting. Moral exporting may bring closure by affirming individual
beliefs but it may also be in service of interpersonal closure (Peterson et
al., 2009). At times of conflict, when interpersonal closure needs are elevated
as threat is elevated, even relatively uncertain modernists should engage in
moral exporting. Traditionalist liberals, who believe in transcendental truths
but take liberal policy stances, may be moral absolutists but only believe it
necessary to share a small segment of their values, limiting the extent to
which they proselytize.
Libertarians in the Worldview Model may be modernists who
accept individual moral orientations but justify this stance with reference to
a rational process. Libertarians may assert each individual’s ability to
discover their own individual rational values. Libertarians may,
further, reject postmodern beliefs that these individual values cannot be
considered objective. These libertarians may either take traditionally
conservative or traditionally liberal policy stances. However, they should be
relatively consistent in their belief that a society that limits their personal
freedom is oppressive. This is an issue on which they should be
motivated to achieve closure.
Seeing themselves as being in conflict with an oppressive
society, libertarians may be under relatively high closure needs and
aggressively seek a solution to the problem of that oppression. Libertarians,
then, should be motivated to achieve closure on why they deserve more freedom,
which could reduce their integrative complexity, if this process is not
challenged by traditionalists, modernists, or postmodernists with other
beliefs. However, relatively powerless and conscious of their perceived
oppression, they should also engage in dialogue with wider society, which could
lead them to develop stances that possess relatively more integrative
complexity.
It should be recalled that the Worldview Model predicts that
modernist cultures should vary. Some should require specific closure
only on the fundamental questions of whether absolute truth exists and whether
it could, possibly, be discovered through inquiry. Others should
require specific closure across a variety of domains. However, although this
model asserts that all individuals should have a dominant worldview, a claim
that should be empirically tested, some individuals may switch worldviews over
the course of a lifetime. Others may hold beliefs that reflect contradictory
worldviews, leading to internal conflict only when their ability to analyze and
evaluate absolute truths is called into question. Still other individuals may
combine traditionalist or modernist orientation with a postmodern one.
A postmodernist, as defined by Golek and Van Bergh (2007),
believes that no one can possess absolute truth. To the extent that a
postmodern worldview is the product of socialization, it should increase a need
to avoid closure and decrease a need for closure. However, there are
no relevant empirical studies that I know of that directly examine postmodern
participants. However, the postmodernist resembles the individuals postulated
by Fiske and Tetlock’s (1997) model of how to manage taboo tradeoffs. The
authors suggested that the equal validity of the conflicting values be
affirmed, as well as, within a group, differing individual preferences for each
value. They further suggested that the group work out an optimum
solution that acknowledged, rather than avoiding, the
tradeoffs. This model specifically denies the ultimate rationality
of any one solution, but suggests that the best solution will represent a
compromise among the conflicting values. The postmodernist individual, the Worldview
Model predicts, would most likely be politically liberal, but political
preferences would vary with interpersonal interactions in a decision-making
context.
Many indigenous peoples combine traditionalist and
postmodern beliefs in order to assert their right to continue to embrace
traditional beliefs and to follow traditional values. Relatively unable to lead
revolutions, colonized indigenous traditionalists living in a postcolonial
society must carve out a place for themselves as knowledgeable authorities without
completely rejecting the philosophical basis of the post-colonial state. These
efforts may militate against western science or seek to claim scientific
legitimacy. Vine Deloria Jr.’s Red Earth, White Liesexemplifies
both approaches. When these cultural conflicts cannot be resolved, closure may
be boldly avoided.
While postmodernist beliefs may fulfill needs to avoid
closure that arise from the undesirable or impractical implications of
traditionalist or modern worldviews, they may also moderate need for closure on
certain political issues. For example, a postmodernist may believe in
freedom of religion, until that religion seems to oppress her, an individual
that she cares about, or a group with which she identifies. Although
she may ultimately take a stance and seek closure, she may ultimately simply
acknowledge her value conflict and seek to find the best solution
possible.